|
Definition together with a topology
on
for which the sum,
product, additive and multiplicative inverse functions are
continuous.
The space is Hausdorff.
If is compact, then
is finite.
has no limit at
.
There exists a non-empty open proper subset of .
Example
Finite fields with the discrete topology.
Linearly ordered fields with the order topology.
If is any field, then the field
of formal Laurent series with the valuation topology
(in fact any valued field). Note that
is
closed, and that the induced topology on
is
the discrete topology.
Let be a topological field, and consider an
algebraic extension
.
Then
as a vector space over
. The product topology then induces a
topological field.
We fix a topological field .
Definition be open, let
and let
. Then
is said
differentiable if there exists a
such that
The number is unique, and we write
.
This is preserved by sums, products, quotients, composition and so on. Moreover differentiability implies continuity. We also have the Cauchy-Riemann equations.
We will next consider more specific contexts: -minimality in particular.
Let be
-minimal
and write
for its algebraic closure
. Any
-rational
function is differentiable.
Consider the case of . If
converges in a neighborhood of zome
, then there is some open
such that
is definable in
.
On , the function
is not definable in any
-minimal
expansion of
. Fact: let
be open such that
is
definable in some
-minimal
expansion of
. Then the
imaginary part of
must be bounded. Indeed,
defining
on
,
and the set
(project onto the
-axis if you must) must be bounded by
-minimality. Conversely, in
, each such
is definable whenever
is definable. In
particular
is defined and injective on the strip
of
with
.
So
is definable.
Question is open and
is real-analytic and
definable in some
-minimal
expansion of
, then when can
be extended definably to some
which is complex-analytic, where
is open? This is open for
definable in
.
Answer . Andre Opris shows in his PhD thesis that this is
the case for a large class of functions called restricted
-
-analytic
functions, which is a proper subset of the set of definable functions in
.
Consider the field of formal Puiseux series over
, where
is a positive infinitesimal. The field
is
real-closed. Let
denote its algebraic closure.
For all
(formal power series), we have a
function
. Write
for the structure
.
Robinson and Lipshitz showed that this is
-minimal.
Any such function
can be dedinably extended to
.
We fix an -minimal expansion
of a real-closed field
, and write
for the
algebraic closure of
.
Everything will be definable.
Definition is a definable and continuous
with
. We sometimes write
. The curve
is called simple if
is injective.
Example . We fix some simple counter-clockwise
semi-algebraic parametrization
of
.
Given any closed curve and a definable
continuous map
. We have maps
choosing so that
.
Write
. For simplicity,
assume that
is not locally constant anywhere.
The only possible discontinuities lie in
,
which by
-minimality, is
finite. Write
be the discontinuities. We add
as a point, in order to define the winding
number of
as follows. For
, write
We define the winding number of
as
xample
Example . Then
.
Also
, and
.
Remark
is a definable family of continuous functions
. Then by
-minimality
the numbers
corresponding to
above are bounded, so the definition of
can be
done uniformly.
Let us give a few properties of those winding numbers.
If is not surjective, then
.
Let be definably holomorphic. Assume that
and
are
homotopy-equivalent, i.e. there is a continuous
with
and
.
Then
. This relies on the
facts that
is dedinably connected in
, and that the function
is locally constant.
For continuous definable ,
we have
.
If one reverses the parametrization of ,
then
.
Definition be definable and continuous, and let
. We want to define the winding
number
of
around
. We define
,
and set
.
Lemma be definable, open and non-empty. Let
be definable and continuous, and let
such that
is
-differentiable
at
. If
, then for all sufficiently small circles
centered at
,
we have
.
Proof. Write .
Since
, there is a
with
for all
. So we can consider
. Also set
Note that for all circles
around
. Since
, for
sufficiently
close to
, the element
is close to
.
In particular, picking a sufficiently small circle
around
, the function
is not surjective. So
.
We conclude that
.
Write for the closed unit disk in
, and
for the unit
circle, parametrized counter-clockwise.
Main Lemma. Let
be definable and
-differentiable
on
. Let
. We have
Example -differentiable
.
Let
. So
is an upper arc in
, and
has one definably connected component, and has
winding number
around any element in the
including those which lie in
.
Proof of the Main Lemma. We first prove i. We can use
an homotopy to shrink continuously, and as the
radius of
tends to
,
the curve
is close to
, so
will not be surjective
(it will only cover a small angle). So the winding number of
is
, hence the
result.
Let us now prove ii. Fix a definably connected and open component of
which contains
. Since
is
definably connected (because
is and
is continuous and definable), the point
is not isolated in
, so
is infinite. Consider the open set
. We claim that the set
has dimention . Indeed assume
for contradiction that
has dimension
. Then in particular
has codimension
.
But
has differential
everywhere, so partitioning
,
we see that
is locally constant, so takes only
finitely many values. So
is finite:
contradicting the previous argument.
The statements of the main lemma are first-order, so we can move to a
sufficiently saturated elementary extension, and consider a generic
point in
over
. Then
is
at
as an
-function. Moreover
is
invertible (i.e.
), then the
inverse function theorem for
-minimal
structures gives that
contains an open set,
whence in particular
contains an open set.
Pick be generic, so
. We claim that
is finite
and that
is non-zero on this set. Assume for
contradiction that
is infinite. Let
. Then
since it
contains the generic point
.
So
is surjectve for all such infinite fibers,
which is impossible since the dimentin of
is
. Assume for contradiction
that there is
with
,
and write
for the set of such
's. Then again
has
dimension
. By definable
choice, there is a
such that for all
, there is a
with
and this yields a similar
contradiction.
03-02: Lecture 5
Removal of singularities à la Riemann.
Let be open and non-empty, let
and let
be definable,
-differentiable and bounded. Then
there is a unique
such that the extension of
to
with
is
-differentiable.
Proof. Set for
and
. Since
is bounded, we have
, so
is
-differentiable
on
, so by the previous
theorem, the function
is
-differentiable at
,
with
. We then extend
by continuity and see that
is
-differentiable at
.
Using the previous result and the maximum principle, one can prove the following:
Theorem is definable and
-differentiable,
then
is also
-differentiable.
We start with an -minimal
fact:
Proof. Assume for contradiction that this is not the
case. So for all there is a definable path
converging to
such that
tends to
.
So
tends to
.
So
. But this is the frontier
of a set of dimension
,
whereas
has dimension
: a contradiction.
We fix an open set , a point
and a definable and
-differentiable
.
Assume that
is not constant around
. We define the order
of
at
as
follows. Recall that for sufficiently large
, the number
is constant
(where
is the circle around
of radius
). We then define
to be that integer.
Write for the continuation on
. We have
,
whence
by a previous theorem.
Again write for the continuation on
. If
, then we claim that
Indeed shrinking (hence
) sufficiently, we can obtain that
lie outside of
.
In particular must be unbounded near
. We claim that
![]() |
(3.1) |
Let be a neighborhood of
, let
and
such that
![]() |
(3.2) |
for all . Set
for all . The function
is
-differentiable,
and bounded by (3.2). So
is a
removable singularity for
.
So
. We conclude since
is unbounded near
that
, whenc
.
Let us show that
Set
on a [épointé] neighborhood of
.
By (3.1), we can extend
to
by setting
.
Now we know that
,
whence
for all sufficiently small
(i.e. whenever
).
Theorem . There is a definable and
-differentiable
with
such that
for all .
Proof. Let be sufficiently
small, so
. Note that
, so setting
on
, we have
. By the previous trichotomy, the function
can be extended to
with
; hence the result.
Corollary is
-differentiable
at
and that
.
Then
where
means that
there is an analytic continuation of
such
that...
Corollary ,
“the” function
cannot be defined as
a
-differentiable map on a
neighborhood of
.
Let be a non-empty open definable set, and let
.
From the proof of Theorem 3.1, we deduce:
Theorem be definable and
-differentiable.
Then
If is a pole, then
for a fixed sequence .
Corollary
from germs at of
-differentiable and definable functions to power
series in
is injective.
Theorem -differentiable function
is a polynomial.
Theorem is definable and
-differentiable,
then
is a polynomial.
Proposition be a definable family of
-differentiable
functions
, then there is an
such that each
has
degree
.
Question
be a definable family of polynomial functions on
. Is there a uniform bound on the degree of
?
Example be an arbitrary sequence of
complex numbers in
with absolute value
. Define
This is definable in , and
for all
, the function
is a polynomial of degree
. But for
the function
is not a polynomial, so this doesn't give a negative
answer to the previous question.
Proposition be a definable family of
-differentiable
functions on
for open sets
. Then there is an
, such that for all
,
either
is locally constant around
or
.
Proposition be a definable family of
-differentiable
functions on
for open sets
. For
,
let
be the Laurent series associated to ,
where
is as in the previous proposition. Then
the function
is definable.
Let us now go back to the classical setting . Let
be a simple closed
curve and let
have finitely many residues
in
.
Recall that
in the previous notations. We have
.
So if is as above and
is
a definable family of simple closed curves, and
is finite and uniformly definable, then the function
is also definable.
Theorem is definable and
-differentiable,
then
is polynomial.
Proof. For all ,
the function
is polynomial by the one variable
corresponding result. By
-minimality,
the degrees of corresponding polynomials when
ranges in
are bounded by some
. So
.
Loooking at
, we can conclude
by induction.
In fact, we have a result from and
which is polynomial in each variable, the function
is in fact polynomial.
Assume that is definable and
-differentiable on a non-empty open set
, and let
such that
is simply connected for some
neighborhood
of
.
Then
exists in
.
Indeed recall that for
definable, and
non-constant and
-differentiable
on
, then
is finite on
. Indeed assume
that
as infinitely many limit points around
. Then sufficiently close to
, one can also arrange that
is injective and that it have non-zero
derivative. So the inverse map of the restriction will be
-differentiable on an open set. Then
sends an infinite subset of
to
, so
must be constant: a contradiction.
Question is holomorphic and bounded. Does
extend to
?
(preserving boundedness).
We now work with , so
. Apparently the results should
still be valid in the more general context.
Definition -manifold is
a definable ,
a finite cover by definable subsets ,
For all , a definable
bijection
into an open subset
of
such that the transition
maps are holomorphic.
Note that the transition maps are definable.
Example ,
graphs of definable holomorphic maps
,
as well as the projective spaces are definable manifolds. If
is a discrete sugroup of
,
then the quotient
can be equipped with a
-manifold
chart by realizing this within
7.1. this speaks to Lou's remark being relevant: can we not define this abstractly rather than always having to find a embedded representation?
Fact: Every compact analytic manifold is definably
biholomorphic (in the sense of manifolds) to a definable -manifold.
Definition definable
-manifolds.
A definable holomorphic function
is a definable
function
which is holomorphic through
charts.
Definition which is an
-submanifold, for which
moreover the tangent space at each
is
-linear.
The only compact definale submanifolds of are
the finite sets.
Theorem be a definable
-manifold.
If
is a definable submanifold, then it has a
natural structure of definable
-manifold,
and the inclusion
is a definable holomorphic
function.
Definition be a definable
-manifold.
A definable analytic subset of
is a definable
closed
such that for all
, there are a definale neighorhood
of
and finitely many definable and holomorphic
functions
with
It can be showed that in fact can be covered by
finitely many such sets
and functions.
Example are definable analytic subsets of
. If
is a
definable compact
-manifold
for
, then every analytic
subset of
is a definable analytic subset of
(again in
).
(By Chow's theorem, every analytic subset of is
an algebraic variety.)
The basic problem: is a definable
-manifold, we have a definable open
, and a definable analytic subset
of
as per Definition 7.6. When is the closure
of
in
an analytic subset of
? So did we “add
singularities” by taking the closure?
Example
and take
to be the unit disk. So
is a definable analytic subset of itself. But the closed
disk is not an analytic subset of
.
We recall a classical result of removal of singularities:
Remmert-Stein theorem. Let
be a
-manifold, let
be a
-analytic
subset, and set
. If
is irreducible analytic subset, and
, then
is an analytic
subset of
.
A bunch of -minimal ROS
results:
Assume that for all non-empty definable open
. Then
is an analytic susbet of
.
Let be a definable analytic subset with
. Then
is an analytic susbet of
.
A corollary of is that
Corollary is a definable family of subsets of a definable
-manifold
, then the set
is
definable.
Proof. Set for each
. Each
is a
locally analytic definable subset of
.
The set
is an analytic subset of
if and only if
is closed, if
is dense in
,
and if
for all non-empty definable open
.
It follows that we have a:
Definable Chow theorem. If
is a definable analytic subset, then
is
algebraic.
Corollary is a definable family of subsets of
, then
is definable.
Exercise -minimal structures.
Assume that we have a lattice where
is an
-basis of
. Write
with its definable structure of
-manifold.
Then we saw that
is isomorphic to an elliptic
curve
.
We may assume that where
. Recall that
and
are isomorphic if and only if there is a
with
(where
is the
standard action of
on
). Moreover, there is a holomorphic and
transcendental surjective map
with
where the isomorphism is as abelian varieties, analytic manifolds. The
function is called the
invariant.
Set
Then each orbit of has excatly one
representative in
. It
follows that
is still surjective (and
injective).
Theorem is definale in
.
Proof. Consider the function . Then
is definable in
by previous results. Now on any bounded part
of
, the
function
is definable on
in
. For
, we have
,
and we see that
is the punctured disk
centered on
.
Recall that in particular
for all
, and
as well. So we
can factor
by
and get an
analytic map
with
Fact: , so
, i.e.
is a pole of
, and we can write
where
are analytic, definable in
. So
is definable in
.